Mulamadhyamakakarika
Mūlamadhyamakakārikā, or Fundamental Verses on the Middle Way, is a key text by Nagarjuna, one of the most important Buddhist philosophers. It now stands at the centre of modern philosophical analysis of the Madhyamaka philosophy, which is rapidly proliferating to match the rich and varied commentarial tradition that the text has accumulated over the centuries since its composition (most likely in the 2nd century).
Contents |
Competing interpretations
The argument is unusually susceptible to interpretation, as it is expressed almost wholly as a series of often cryptic refutations. We may classify the divergent treatments of the Madhyamakakārikā under three headings: those presenting the text as an appendix to a previously established philosophical tradition, those reading the text as a poem to subsequent philosophical developments, and those that would present it as philosophical teaching unto itself. For a brief example of each, we may consider that the modern Theravādins have represented the text as a mere recapitulation of early Buddhist anātman-theory (i.e., the Buddha’s rejection of a transcendent self), various Mahāyāna schools have regarded the text as the basis for their metaphysics (as with the Yogacara in India, or the Hua-Yen in China), and the Prāsaṅgika school (led by Candrakīrti) regarded the Mūlamadhyamakakārikā as a definitive manual on method, allowing of little in the way of further development and taking little interest in text’s sources in the Śrāvaka Sutras.
It is to be observed that Nāgārjuna’s other works are not nearly so constrained in form, and have not been given a place of equal prominence in modern scholarship. This is sometimes attributable to misgivings over the authenticity of other texts (many of which are not extant in Sanskrit), but is sometimes due to sectarian biases. The openness of the Mūlamadhyamakakārikā to interpretation and re-interpretation has garnered the interest of diverse religious and secular schools, and has at the same time fostered a reluctance to interpret it in light of the same author’s other, less ambiguous writings.
Form and content of the text
The early chapters
The early chapters of the Mūlamadhyamakakārikā (hereafter, MMK), deal mostly with basic metaphysical categories like causation, time, and agency. In general, they pose questions regarding the basic categories of Indian philosophy, trying to acertain what are the conditions necessary for these concepts to be coherent and non-contradictory. Nāgārjuna’s conclusion is uniformly negative; he finds that none of these ideas are self-sufficient, and as such none can found any of the others; there are no viable foundations. These chapters are:
- Pratyayaparīkṣā: Analysis of conditions
- Gatāgataparīkṣā: Analysis of going and not going
- Cakṣurādīndriyaparīkṣā: Analysis of the eye and the other sense-organs
- Skandhaparīkṣā: Analysis of the skandhas ((mental) “aggregates”)
- Dhātuparīkṣā: Analysis of the dhatūs (“constitutents” or “strata” (in the sense of metaphysical substrata))
- Rāgaraktaparīkṣā: Analysis of passion and the impassioned
- Saṃskṛtaparīkṣā: Analysis of the conditioned
- Karmakārakaparīkṣā: Analysis of action and actor
- Pūrvaparīkṣā: Analysis of the past
- Agnīndhanaparīkṣā: Analysis of fire and fuel
- Pūrvaparakoṭiparīkṣā: Analysis of past and future limits
- Duḥkhaparīkṣā: Analysis of suffering
The later chapters
In these chapters, Nāgārjuna begins to move away from simply negating others’ concepts and beings, slowly, to put forward some assertions of his own. In these chapters, Nāgārjuna puts forth his boldest reasoning, including such assertions as:
- The emptiness of all things (i.e., all things, including the Buddha, are without a nature) (MMK#22:26)
- The identity of pratītyasamutpāda with śunyatā (MMK#24:18)
- The indifferentiability of nirvāṇa from saṃsāra (MMK#16:10)(MMK#25:19-20)
- The tentative or merely conventional nature of all truth (MMK#22:11).
These chapters are as follows; note the clustering of 24-26, and also the nature of the last chapter:
- 13. Saṃskāraparīkṣā: Analysis of disposition
- 14. Saṃsargaparīkṣā: Analysis of admixture
- 15. Svabhāvaparīkṣā: Analysis of being or essence
- 16. Bandhanamokṣaparīkṣā: Analysis of bondage and liberation
- 17. Karmaphalaparīkṣa: Analysis of action and its fruit
- 18. Ātmaparīkṣā: Analysis of the soul.
- 19. Kālaparīkṣā: Analysis of time
- 20. Sāmagrīparīkṣā: Analysis of holism
- 21. Saṃbhavavibhavaparīkṣā: Analysis of becoming and un-becoming
- 22. Tathāgataparīkṣā: Analysis of the Tathāgata
- 23. Viparyāsaparīkṣā: Analysis of Error
- 24. Āryasatyaparīkṣā: Analysis of the Noble Truths
- 25. Nirvānaparīkṣā: Analysis of nirvāṇa
- 26. Dvādaśāṅgaparīkṣā: Analysis of the twelvefold chain (of dependent origination)
- 27. Dṛṣṭiparīkṣā: Analysis of views
Nāgārjuna’s opponents
To some extent the refutations that comprise the bulk of the text may be supposed to have been intended for the benefit of definite, historical schools of opponents. The amount that we may know about Nāgārjuna’s contemporaries will remain limited, and it is reasonable to suppose that Nāgārjuna largely made his opponents’ doctrines a convenience for unfolding his own, as he took no trouble (in this text) to give a balanced view or summary of what he argued against. Most commonly, we have only a few words of each objection from the interlocutor before Nāgārjuna proceeds to refute the error at length. The extent to which the author may have misrepresented his opponents out of convenience may never be known. Some portions of the Mūlamadhyamakakārikā certainly appear to have been polemics against the ontology (and cosmology) of the Māha-Vibhāṣa-Abhidharma-Śāstra, and others seem to target the Pudgalavāda school. The influence of early Lankāvatāra texts may be surmised, but the paucity of early manuscripts of the latter has left its historical significance open as another matter of speculation. It may also be the case that Nagarjuna considered himself part of the longstanding Buddhist tradition of composing manuals of the correct answers to common questions from laypeople, and refutations of false views directed at monks by skeptics, or members of rival religions. “Manuals” of this nature are found in Abhidhamma, as well as in quasi-canonical works such as the Milindhapanha (“The questions of King Menander”), and are prefigured to some extent in the Suttapitaka by tracts such as the “Brahma’s Net of False Views Sutra”. Thus, we must leave open the possibility that Nagarjuna had no specific opponents or rival schools in mind, but instead composed the verses as a memoriter “manual” to prepare students or monks for debates, questions, or fallacies they might encounter from various camps, within or without the Buddhist community.
Mūlamadhyamakakārikā and epistemology
The Madhyamakakārikā provides us with a theory of knowledge and a “critique of reason”. Those who have read the text as a philosophy unto itself (e.g., the Prasangikas) have emphasized the extent to which understanding the limitations of knowledge and reasoning precludes the need for metaphysics or even for “truths”, “standpoints”, and other certainties. For the Prasangikas, all teachings are merely conventional. Their predominant method of argumentation is by reductio ad absurdum, “prasaṅga” in Sanskrit. For them, the exposition of śūnyatā is merely a way of pointing to the absence of any essence or foundation, whether in terms of metaphysical substance or in terms of epistemological truth.
However, many Mahayana schools have made this very teaching of emptiness the basis of their systems of speculative constructions, cosmologies, ethics, and metaphysics. The Theravada interpretation, on the other hand, (which has come to prominence only recently) suggests that Nāgārjuna neither intended to preclude metaphysics (with a perfect system of reasoning) nor to found a new system of thought. The purpose of the text, so this argument goes, was to counteract certain misinterpretations that had sprung up around the Buddha’s original teaching of anatman (literally “no soul” or “no self”). Simplicity might seem to favour the latter treatment, but to apply Nāgārjuna’s interpretation of anatman (namely, extending it to all entities equally, including dharmas) to the Shravaka Sutras (not to mention the Abhidharmapitaka) would either throw the Theravadin canon into considerable self-contradiction, or call for a thoroughgoing re-interpretation of the Buddha’s original teaching.
The Madhyamakakārikā’s ultimate purpose, we should remember, was not to stake out a sectarian position (a “dṛṣṭi”, or “view”). Nāgārjuna repeatedly and emphatically states that to make a “fixed view” of his teaching is to miss its point. The purpose of the Madhyamakakārikā’s short course in reasoning is soteriological: to demonstrate the fallacy of clinging to views (or any standpoint whatever, however valid or true) and, in so doing, to remove an obstacle to enlightenment. For this reason it may be described as an “anti-philosophy” as well as a philosophy in its own right.
As the text concludes,
27:30
Sarvadṛṣṭiprahānāya yaḥ saddharmamadeśatAnukampām upādāya taṃ namasyāmi gautamaṃI bow to Gautama, who, having taken up compassion, taught the true dharma for forsaking all views.
Translations
Author | Title | Publisher | Date | Notes |
---|---|---|---|---|
Garfield, Jay L. | The Fundamental Wisdom of the Middle Way | Oxford University Press | 1995 | A translation of the Tibetan version together with commentary. |
Inada, Kenneth K. | Nagarjuna: A Translation of his Mulamadhyamakakarika With an Introductory Essay | The Hokuseido Press | 1970 | Romanized text and translation. |
Kalupahana, David J. | Nagarjuna: The Philosophy of the Middle Way | State University of New York Press | 1986 | Romanized text, translation, and commentary. |
McCagney, N. | Nagarjuna and the Philosophy of Openness | Rowman & Littlefield | 1997 | Romanized text, translation and philosophical analysis. |
Sprung, M. | Lucid Exposition of the Middle Way | Prajna Press, Boulder | 1979 | Partial translation of the verses together with Chandrakirti’s commentary. |
Streng, Frederick | Emptiness: A Study in Religious Meaning | Abdingdon Press | 1967 | Translation and considerable analysis. |
Quotations
1:1
- Neither from itself nor from another,
- Nor from both,
- Nor without a cause,
- Does anything whatever, anywhere arise.
15:10
- अस्तीति शाश्वतग्राहो नास्तीत्युच्चेददर्शनं
- astīti śāśvatagrāho nāstītyuccedadarśanaṁ
- (To say) “Is,” is eternity-grasping; (to say) “Is not,” is a nihilistic view.
- तस्माद् अस्तित्वनास्तित्वे नाश्रीयेत विचक्षणः।
- tasmād astitvanāstitve nāśrīyeta vicakṣaṇaḥ|
- Therefore, those of discerning vision would not have recourse to Is-ness and Is-not-ness.
16:10
- न निर्वाणसमारोपो न संसारापकषणम्
- na nirvāṇasamāropo na saṁsārāpakaṣaṇam
- यत्र कस्तत्र संसारो निर्वाणं किं विकल्प्यते
- yatra kastatra saṁsāro nirvāṇaṁ kiṁ vikalpyate
- Where there is neither an addition of nirvana nor a removal of samsara; There, what samsara is discriminated from what nirvana?
18:6-12
- ātmetya api prajñapitam anātmetyapi deśitam
- Although (the term) “self” is caused to be known (of, about), and although (a doctrine or teaching of) “no self” is taught,
- buddhair nātmā na cānātmā kaścid ity api deśitaṁ| 6
- No “self” or any “nonself” whatsoever has been taught by the Buddhas.
- nivṛtam abhidhātavyaṁ nivṛtte cittagocare
- The designable is ceased when/where the range of thought is ceased,
- anutpannāniruddhā hi nirvāṇam iva dharmatā| 7
- Nirvana is like phenomenality, unarisen and unstopping.
- sarvaṁ tathyaṁ na vā tathyaṁ tathyaṁ cātathyam eva ca
- Everything is actual, or not actual, or actual and not actual
- naivātathyaṁ naiva tathyam etad buddhānuśāsanaṁ| 8
- Or neither actual nor not actual; this is the Buddha’s teaching.
- aparapratyayaṁ śāntaṁ prapañcair aprapañcitaṁ
- Independent, peaceful, not delusionally diversified by delusional diversification
- nirvikalpam anānārtham etat tattvasya lakśaṇaṁ| 9
- Devoid of mental construction, without variation, this is the mark of thatness.
- pratītya yad yad bhavati na hi tāvat tad eva tad
- Whatsoever becomes dependently, is not insofar, that and only that.
- na cānyad api tat tasmān noccinnaṁ nāpi śāśvataṁ| 10
- Nor is it the other; therefore, it is neither exterminated nor eternal.
- anekārtham anānārtham anuccedam aśāśvatam
- Not singular, not plural, not exterminated, not eternal,
- etat tal lokanāthānāṁ bhuddhānāṁ śāsanāmṛtaṁ| 11
- This is the immortal teaching of the Buddhas, lords of the world.
- sambhuddhānām anutpāde śrāvakāṇāṁ punaḥ kśaye
- And again, when the disciples are destroyed and full Buddhas do not arrive,
- jñānaṁ pratyekabuddhānām asamsargāt pravartate|12
- The gnosis (knowledge, etc.) of the independently enlightened Buddhas proceeds without association (with teachings).
22:11
- “Empty” should not be said (or “would be impossible to say”), nor should “Nonempty”,
- nor “both and neither”; but they are spoken of for the purpose of praj~naptification. (Causing some gnosis/wisdom, or causing gnosis/wisdom of something; “teaching”)
22:16
- तथागतो यत्स्वभावस्तत्स्वभावमिदं जगत
- tathāgato yat svabhāvas tat svabhāvam idam jagat
- What is the nature of the thus-gone one (the Buddha), that is the nature of the world.
- तथागतो निःस्वभावो निःस्वभावम् इदं जगत्। १६
- tathāgato niḥsvabhāvo niḥsvabhāvam idaṁ jagat| 16
- The thus-gone one is devoid of nature; the world is devoid of nature.
24:18
- What is dependent origination, that we call emptiness.
- It is the middle way proceeding, having had recourse to teaching. (Note: probably teaching by upāya, or “expedients”)
25:19-20
- न संसारस्य निर्वाणात् किं चिद् अस्ति विशेषणं
- na saṁsārasya nirvāṇāt kiṁ cid asti viśeṣaṇaṁ
- There is nothing whatsoever of samsara distinguishing (it) from nirvana.
- न निर्वाणस्य संसारात् किं चिद् अस्ति विशेषणं। १९
- na nirvāṇasya saṁsārāt kiṁ cid asti viśeṣaṇaṁ| 19
- There is nothing whatsoever of nirvana distinguishing it from samsara.
- निर्वाणस्य च या कोटिः।कोटिः। संसरणस्य च
- nirvāṇasya ca yā koṭiḥ koṭiḥ| saṁsaraṇasya ca
- (That?) is the limit which is the limit of nirvana and the limit of samsara;
- न तयोर् अन्तरं किंचित् सुसूक्ष्मम् अपि विद्यते। २०
- na tayor antaraṁ kiñcit susūkśmam api vidyate| 20
- Even a very subtle interval is not found of (between) them.
25:22-24
- śūnyeṣu sarvadharmeṣu kim anantaṁ kimantavat
- kim anantam antavac ca nānantaṁ nāntavacca kiṁ| 22
- kiṁ tad eva kim anyat kiṁ śāśvataṁ kim aśāśvataṁ
- aśāśvataṁ śāśvataṁ ca kiṁ vā nobhayam apyataḥ ‘tha| 23
- sarvopalambhpaśamaḥ prapañcopaśamaḥ śivaḥ
- na kva cit kasyacit kaścid dharmo buddhena deśitaḥ|
-
- When all dharmas are empty, what is endless? What has an end?
- What is endless and with an end? What is not endless and not with an end?
- What is “it”? What is “other”? What is permanent? What is impermanent?
- What is impermanent and permanent? What is neither?
- Auspicious is the pacification of phenomenal metastasis, the pacification of all apprehending;
- There is no dharma whatsoever taught by the Buddha to whomever whenever, wherever.
See also
- Buddhist philosophy
- Madhyamaka
- Nāgārjuna
Indian philosophy
Hindu philosophy | Samkhya | Nyaya | Vaisheshika | Yoga | Mimamsa | Advaita Vedanta | Vishishtadvaita | Dvaita | Carvaka | Logic |
Jain philosophy | |
Buddhist philosophy | Shunyata |
Philosophers | Akshapada Gotama | Patanjali | Yajnavalkya | Kanada | Kapila | Jaimini | Vyasa | Nagarjuna | Madhavacharya | Kumarajiva | Padmasambhava | Vasubandhu | Adi Shankara| Ramanuja| More.. |
Texts | Yoga Sutra | Nyaya Sutra | Vaiseshika Sutra | Samkhya Sutra | Mimamsa Sutra | Brahma Sutra | Mūlamadhyamakakārikā | More.. |
中論